No. 1 (2023)
Articles

Toward an Epicurean MAC Model of Boredom

Alex Gillham
St. Bonaventure University

Published 2023-01-13

How to Cite

Gillham, A. (2023). Toward an Epicurean MAC Model of Boredom. Journal of Boredom Studies, (1). Retrieved from https://boredomsociety.com/jbs/index.php/journal/article/view/17

Abstract

I have previously argued that an Epicurean who has achieved the final telos will still find philosophy worthwhile on hedonic grounds because philosophy prevents painful boredom they might otherwise experience. In response, Justin Bell objected that the Epicureans do not need the kind of explanation I developed because lasting tranquility is rare if not impossible, and even if this were false, it would be better to take philosophy to be worthwhile to the tranquil because of the curiosity it satisfies rather than the boredom it prevents. I reply here that the Epicureans do need the kind of explanation I developed and that Bell’s explanation is less attractive than mine. However, I also concede that my explanation requires an account of Epicurean boredom, which I proceed to sketch here. Borrowing from Westgate and Wilson’s MAC model, I contend that if doing philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil Epicurean because it prevents boredom, three things must be true: 1) boredom must be an aversive state; 2) the Epicurean must be able to attend to philosophy while tranquil, and 3) philosophizing must have value for the tranquil. I argue that all three conditions are satisfied by the view that philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil because of the painful boredom it prevents.

References

  1. Aristotle (1982). The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton University Press.
  2. Bailey, C. (1928). The Greek Atomists and Epicurus. Russell and Russell.
  3. Barbalet, J. (1999). Boredom and Social Meaning. British Journal of Sociology, 50, 631–646. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-4446.1999.00631.x
  4. Bell, J. (2021). Epicurean Philosophy, Change, and Curiosity. Southwest Philosophy Review, 37(2), 37–40. https://doi.org/10.5840/swphilreview202137233
  5. Bignone, E. (1973). L’Aristotle perduto e la formazione filosofica di Epicuro (vol. 1). La Nuova Italia.
  6. Chater, N., and Loewenstein, G. (2016). The Under-Appreciated Drive for Sense-Making. Journal of Economic Behavior & Organization, 126, 137–154. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2015.10.016
  7. Chin, A., Markey, A., Bhargava, S., Kassam, K. S., and Loewenstein, G. (2017). Bored in the USA: Experience Sampling and Boredom in Everyday Life. Emotion, 17(2), 359–368. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000232
  8. Diano, C. (1943). Note Epicuree. Annali Della R. Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa. Lettere, Storia e Filosofia, 12(3), 111–123.
  9. Eastwood, J., Frischen, A., Fenske, M., and Smilek, D. (2012). The Unengaged Mind: Defining Boredom in Terms of Attention. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 7, 482–495. https://doi.org/10.1177/17456916124560
  10. Fisher, C. (1993). Boredom at Work: A Neglected Concept. Human Relations, 46, 395–417. https://doi.org/10.1177/001872679304600305
  11. Gillham, A. R. (2021). Epicurean Tranquility and the Pleasure of Philosophy. Southwest Philosophy Review, 37(1), 149–158. https://doi.org/10.5840/swphilreview202137116
  12. Hamilton, J. (1981). Attention, Personality, and the Self-Regulation of Mood: Absorbing Interest and Boredom. Progress in Experimental Personality Research, 10, 281–315.
  13. Havermans, R. C., Vancleef, L., Kalamatianos, A, and Nederkoorn, C. (2015). Eating and Inflicting Pain out of Boredom. Appetite, 52–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.appet.2014.11.007
  14. Inwood, B., and Gerson, L. (1994). The Epicurus Reader. Hackett.
  15. Leary, M., Rogers, P., Canfield, R., and Coe, C. (1986). Boredom in Interpersonal Encounters: Antecedents and Social Implications. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 968–975. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.51.5.968
  16. Lucretius. (2009). De rerum natura. Cambridge University Press.
  17. Locke, E., and Latham, G. (1990). A Theory of Goal Setting and Task Performance. Prentice.
  18. Nederkoorn, C., Vancleef, L., Wilkenhöner, A., Claes, L., and Havermans, R. C. (2016). Self-Inflicted Pain out of Boredom. Psychiatry Research, 237, 127–132. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.psychres.2016.01.063
  19. Rist, J. (1972). Epicurus: An Introduction. Cambridge University Press.
  20. Smith, C., and Ellsworth, P. (1985). Patterns of Cognitive Appraisal in Emotion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 48, 813–828. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.48.4.813
  21. Van Tilburg, W. A. P., and Igou, E. R. (2012). On Boredom: Lack of Challenge and Meaning as Distinct Boredom Experiences. Motivation and Emotion, 36, 181–194. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-011-9234-9
  22. Van Tilburg, W. A. P., and Igou, E. R. (2017). Boredom Begs to Differ: Differentiation from Other Negative Emotions. Emotion, 17, 309–322. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000233
  23. Westgate, E. C., and Wilson, T. D. (2018). Boring Thoughts and Bored Minds: The MAC Model of Boredom and Cognitive Engagement. Psychological Review, 125(5), 689–713. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000097
  24. Wilson, T. D., Reinhard, D. A., Westgate, E. C., Gilbert, D. T., Ellerbeck, N., Hahn, C., Brown, C. L., and Shaked, A. (2014). Just Think: The Challenges of the Disengaged Mind. Science, 345, 75–77. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1250830