Journal of Boredom
Studies
Issue 1, 2023, pp. 1–13
https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.7521879
https://www.boredomsociety.com/jbs
Toward an Epicurean
MAC Model of Boredom
Alex R
Gillham
St. Bonaventure
University
https://orcid.org/0000-0003-2234-6945
How to cite this paper: Gillham, A. R. (2023). Toward
an Epicurean MAC Model of Boredom. Journal of Boredom Studies, 1. https://doi.org/10.5281/zenodo.7521879
Abstract: I have previously argued that an Epicurean who
has achieved the final telos will
still find philosophy worthwhile on hedonic grounds because philosophy prevents
painful boredom they might otherwise experience. In response, Justin Bell objected
that the Epicureans do not need the kind of explanation I developed because
lasting tranquility is rare if not impossible, and even if this were false, it
would be better to take philosophy to be worthwhile to the tranquil because of
the curiosity it satisfies rather than the boredom it prevents. I reply here
that the Epicureans do need the kind of explanation I developed and that Bell’s
explanation is less attractive than mine. However, I also concede that my
explanation requires an account of Epicurean boredom, which I proceed to sketch
here. Borrowing from Westgate and Wilson’s MAC model, I contend that if doing
philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil Epicurean because it prevents boredom,
three things must be true: 1) boredom must be an aversive state; 2) the
Epicurean must be able to attend to philosophy while tranquil, and 3)
philosophizing must have value for the tranquil. I argue that all three
conditions are satisfied by the view that philosophy is worthwhile to the
tranquil because of the painful boredom it prevents.
Keywords: boredom, curiosity, Epicurus, MAC model, tranquility.
1. Introduction
I developed (2021) an interpretation of Epicurean ethics according to which boredom is a
mental pain that doing philosophy prevents. Without this interpretation, I
argued that philosophizing would not be worthwhile to those who have already
achieved the final Epicurean telos defined
as tranquility, which consists in freedom from bodily and mental pain, and this
would be inconsistent with several primary Epicurean texts claiming that doing
philosophy is always worthwhile. In a response to me, Justin Bell (2021) objected that positing boredom as a mental pain that doing philosophy
prevents is unnecessary because Epicurean physics make achieving the sort of
tranquility I considered rare if not impossible. Moreover, even if achieving
such tranquility were not rare or impossible, Bell contended that doing
philosophy would more plausibly be worthwhile to those who have achieved the
final Epicurean telos because
philosophizing satisfies their curiosity, not because it prevents them from
experiencing painful boredom. In this article, I argue that although Bell is
correct that achieving tranquility might be rare, my proposal that boredom is a
mental pain that doing philosophy prevents, which makes philosophizing
worthwhile to the tranquil Epicurean, is promising and deserves further
consideration, consideration I provide in this article. Borrowing from Westgate
and Wilson’s (2018) MAC model of boredom, I identify
some conditions that an Epicurean account of boredom would need to satisfy in
order for philosophy to be worthwhile because of the boredom it prevents the
tranquil from experiencing: 1) boredom must be a painful state; 2) the tranquil
Epicurean must be capable of attending to the activity of philosophy when
bored, and 3) philosophy must have meaning for the tranquil Epicurean. I argue
that philosophy can play the role I previously argued it does within
Epicureanism on such a MAC model of boredom. I conclude that when the
Epicureans are equipped with such a model, my proposal that philosophy is
worthwhile to the tranquil because of the painful boredom it prevents becomes
more plausible.
2. Tranquility,
Boredom, Curiosity, and Philosophy
Epicurean axiology is
thoroughly hedonistic. Pleasure is the only intrinsic good,[1]
but there are two kinds of pleasure: kinetic and katastematic. Understanding
the difference between kinetic and katastematic pleasure requires understanding
the role that desire plays in the good life.[2]
Since the Epicureans are hedonists, they think that our ultimate goal in life
is to experience pleasure. When we want an object and do not get it, we
experience pain, and the experience of pain is to be avoided for the hedonist.
For Epicureans, the solution is to control our desires so that we only want
what is natural and necessary for happiness. If we can meet our basic needs and
do not have to worry about being able to do so, we can be as happy as gods.
Thus, one Epicurean doctrine reads: “The cry of the flesh: not to be hungry,
not to be thirsty, not to be cold. For if someone has these things and is
confident of having them in the future, he might contend even with Zeus for
happiness” (VS 33 [1994]).[3]
To make sense of this claim, more needs to be said about the nature of
happiness. According to the Epicureans, the final telos is tranquility; freedom from bodily and mental pain is that
for the sake of which everything else is worthwhile. Indeed, Epicurus himself
writes that “we do everything for the sake of neither being in pain nor in
terror”, clarifying that tranquility is our ultimate goal (Ep. Men. 128 [1994]). Since pleasure is the intrinsic good and pain impedes pleasure, we
want to avoid as much pain as we possibly can in our lives. There are two kinds
of pain: bodily and mental. The closer we get to eliminating all pain of both
kinds, the nearer we get to achieving tranquility. We experience kinetic
pleasure in the process of and katastematic pleasure as a result of eliminating
these pains.[4]
Think of the bodily pain you experience from hunger. You experience kinetic
(active) pleasure in the process of eating while hungry and then katastematic
(static) pleasure after having eaten, once full. If you were to eliminate all
bodily and mental pain from your life, then you would achieve complete
tranquility. In turn, your life would be as pleasant as possible, and, as a
result, you would be as happy as you can be. Freedom from all bodily and mental
pain is the ultimate goal. All value is derived from this ideal. An experience,
activity, etc. is valuable and worthwhile only if it brings us nearer to achieving
tranquility, conceived of as the absence of bodily and mental pain.
I have argued (2021) that
all these features of Epicurean axiology set up the following problem. Since an
experience, activity, etc. is worthwhile only if it brings us nearer to
achieving tranquility, and tranquility is just the absence of bodily and mental
pain, then it follows that nothing would be worthwhile to someone who has
eliminated all bodily and mental pain, thereby becoming tranquil. In order to
be worthwhile to the tranquil, there would need to be some bodily and/or mental
pain that doing philosophy eliminates, but the tranquil Epicurean has already
rid themself of all such pains. Nevertheless, doing philosophy continues to be
worthwhile to the person who has already achieved tranquility according to
several Epicurean texts. One Epicurean doctrine, for example, holds that “[i]n
a joint philosophical investigation he who is defeated comes out ahead in so
far as he has learned something new” (VS 74 [1994]). Those
who lose an argument learn, thereby benefitting. If learning is beneficial then
the advanced Epicurean who has already achieved tranquility might find learning
worthwhile, but nothing could be worthwhile to such an Epicurean. On hedonistic
grounds, an experience, activity, etc. could only be worthwhile to such an
Epicurean if it were to bring them closer to tranquility, but the Epicurean in
question has already achieved tranquility. Furthermore, one of Epicurus’
letters also provides evidence that philosophy is always worthwhile. It reads:
Let no one
delay the study of philosophy while young nor weary of it when old. For no one
is either too young or too old for the health of the soul. He who says either
that the time for philosophy has not yet come or that it has passed is like
someone who says that the time for happiness has not yet come or that it has
passed. Therefore, both young and old must philosophize, the latter so that
although old he may stay young in good things owing to gratitude for what has
occurred, the former so that although young he too may be like an old man owing
to his lack of fear of what is to come. Therefore one must practice the things
which produce happiness, since if that is present we have everything and if it
is absent we do everything in order to have it (Ep. Men. 122 [1994]).
A few specific claims from
Ep. Men. 122 are important for my interpretation. First, Epicurus writes that
it is always the time do philosophy, for it is one of the things that produces
happiness, which is just tranquility, defined as freedom from bodily and mental
pain; to be happy is to be tranquil according to the Epicureans. Nonetheless,
the advanced Epicurean who has achieved tranquility has already made their life
as happy as possible in virtue of eliminating all bodily and mental pains. The
only possible obstacles to happiness are these pains, the tranquil Epicurean
has freed themself from all pain, and yet Ep. Men. 122 implies that doing
philosophy is still worthwhile to them. After all, if it is always the time to
do philosophy, then philosophy must always be worthwhile, and if doing
philosophy is always worthwhile, then it must be worthwhile to the advanced
Epicurean who has already achieved tranquility, even though it is difficult to
see how anything could be worthwhile to them. Finally, the most accomplished
Epicureans continued to do philosophy even after achieving tranquility,
including Epicurus himself, and it would be strange if these individuals were
to undertake activity that is not in fact worthwhile, for if doing so were not
worthwhile then presumably they would not do it. On my reading, all of these
considerations give reason to believe that doing philosophy would continue to
be worthwhile even for the Epicurean who has already achieved tranquility, but the
Epicureans appear to be lacking a viable explanation for why anything, let
alone doing philosophy specifically, would be worthwhile to the tranquil.
The Epicureans have the resources to explain coherently
why doing philosophy is worthwhile even to the advanced Epicurean who has
achieved tranquility, although no such explanation exists explicitly in the
primary texts. What makes doing philosophy worthwhile even to the tranquil, I
have argued (2021), is that it prevents the Epicurean
who has freed themself from all bodily and mental pain from lapsing into
boredom, which would be painful. Suppose someone were to achieve tranquility
and then do nothing at all day after day. Life would become painfully boring
for such a person. However, pain is the hedonist’s enemy, an experience to be
avoided, all other things being equal. Therefore, even the advanced Epicurean
who has already achieved tranquility has reasons to avoid this sort of boredom
on hedonic grounds. In turn, if the advanced Epicurean who has already achieved
tranquility has hedonic reasons to prevent boredom, then avoiding boredom is
worthwhile on hedonic grounds for such a person. Consequently, if doing philosophy
prevents boredom for the advanced Epicurean who has already achieved
tranquility, then doing philosophy would be worthwhile on hedonic grounds for them.
In other words, I think that the advanced Epicurean who has already achieved
tranquility might find doing philosophy worthwhile because it helps them to
maintain the tranquility they already enjoy. Without philosophizing, the
advanced Epicurean who has already achieved tranquility might counterfactually
get bored, which would be painful, and thereby lose their tranquility. Doing
philosophy is worthwhile because it preserves tranquility.
Bell (2021) raises two objections against my argument
for the claim that doing philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil because it
helps them avoid painful boredom they might counterfactually experience. First,
Bell argues that tranquility is not a static state in which the Epicurean can
persist. Epicurean physics are thoroughly atomistic and chaotic. Everything
that exists is composed of atoms and void; the formers are always in motion.
Constant motion means constant change. As a result, everything that exists is
always undergoing change, the tranquil person included. In turn, the Epicurean
who eliminates all their bodily and mental pain cannot simply count on
tranquility to last. They must maintain their tranquil state against a
constantly changing world. As things change, they are exposed to new sources of
bodily and mental pain, and the advanced Epicurean must safeguard their
tranquility against such pain. In other words, Bell takes me to overstate how
lasting and/or resilient tranquility actually is.
Bell’s first objection against my proposal is on the
right track. According to the Epicureans, all physical objects are in constant
motion, to move is to undergo change, and so all physical objects undergo
constant change. However, this does not mean that one cannot persist in a
tranquil state over time and/or that tranquility cannot have some permanence.
On the one hand, it is certainly possible to achieve tranquility and then lose
it. On the other hand, that this is possible does not mean that achieving a
resilient tranquility that persists in the face of constant change is
impossible. An Epicurean doctrine holds that “[h]e who has learned the limits
of life knows that it is easy to provide that which removes the feeling of pain
owing to want and make one’s whole life perfect” (KD XXI [1994]). If to make one’s whole life perfect is to achieve tranquility, then
the point of KD XXI is that once we revise our desires so that we only want
what is natural and/or necessary for happiness, our lives will be perfect and
we can remain tranquil no matter what fortune throws our way. Luck is a feature
of life to the extent that we simply cannot control everything that happens to
us, but we can train ourselves to respond to all events in a way that enables
us to remain happy. Another Epicurean doctrine claims that “[c]hance has a
small impact on the wise man” (KD XVI [1994]). The
student of Epicureanism who has really taken its teachings to heart and trained
themself in accordance with them can remain tranquil regardless of what happens
to them. Tranquility need not but can be permanent. The Epicureans even
believed that “if the wise man is tortured on the rack, he is happy” (DL 10.118
[1994]). Supposing that to be happy is to be
tranquil here, DL 10.118 means that one can remain tranquil even despite being
tortured, and if this is possible, then tranquility can be considerably
permanent.[5]
Moreover, Epicurus himself writes that the person who practices Epicurean
precepts day and night will never be disturbed, achieving a godlike happiness.
He instructs the Epicurean to
[p]ractise
these and the related precepts day and night, by yourself and with a
like-minded friend, and you will never be disturbed either when awake or in
sleep, and you will live as a god among men. For a man who lives among immortal
goods is in no respect like a mere mortal animal (Ep. Men. 135 [1994]).
In Epicurean theology,
the gods are incapable of experiencing pain of any kind, and, as a result, they
can never be disturbed and thus enjoy perfect, permanent tranquility. If humans
are also capable of reaching a point where they are never disturbed, as Ep.
Men. 135 implies, then achieving tranquility that persists in the face of an
ever-changing cosmos is not only possible but quite feasible. Consequently,
insofar as tranquility can persist over time, it seems that the Epicureans do
need the sort of explanation I have offered. The advanced Epicurean who
achieves tranquility will continue to do philosophy, which must be hedonically
worthwhile, lest the tranquil Epicurean undertakes an activity without
sufficient reasons. On my solution, doing philosophy would be worthwhile even
to someone who has already achieved tranquility because philosophizing
counteracts a painful boredom they might experience without doing philosophy.
Bell’s (2021, p. 38) second objection is that
“curiosity and not boredom is the better candidate for the pain” that the sage
relieves by doing tranquility, which in turns makes philosophizing worthwhile
to them. Presumably, for Bell, curiosity would be a mental pain because being
curious about something entails wanting to know something and not knowing it,
which constitutes an unsatisfied desire, a source of pain for Epicureans. In
other words, Bell argues that even if the Epicureans need an explanation for
why doing philosophy is worthwhile to the advanced Epicurean who achieves
lasting tranquility—which Bell denies is likely or even possible in the first
place—doing philosophy is more plausibly worthwhile to an advanced Epicurean
who achieves tranquility because it satisfies their curiosity, not because it
saves them from experiencing painful boredom. Bell offers two arguments for
this objection. First, Bell claims that curiosity demands an answer, the lack
of which we often find bothersome. Doing philosophy helps us find the answer to
the things about which we are curious, thereby sating our underlying curiosity.
Being bothered by a lack of answer constitutes a mental pain for us, and doing
philosophy helps us to eliminate this pain by seeking the truth, which is ripe
for Epicurean analysis: finding an answer to a question about which we are
curious would bring the experience of a katastematic pleasure because our
desire for the answer in question is satisfied by doing of philosophy. Second,
Bell argues that curiosity rather than boredom is more plausibly the mental
pain that doing philosophy prevents because there is a feedback loop between
curiosity and philosophy and because the connection between curiosity and
philosophy is tighter than the connection between boredom and philosophy. As to
the feedback loop, Bell’s point is that the more we do philosophy, the more
curious we become, and the more curious we become, the more we need to do
philosophy. As to the tighter connection, Bell’s point seems to be that the
pain of curiosity is more specifically relieved by doing philosophy, whereas
the pain of boredom could be relieved in a bunch of ways that do not even
involve doing philosophy, e.g., by taking a nap, having a walk, or even seeking
vice.
I have two objections against Bell’s claim that it would
be better to posit curiosity rather than boredom as the mental pain that doing
philosophy saves the tranquil from experiencing. First, I think Bell is correct
that curiosity arises from wanting to know an answer, that not knowing this is
bothersome, and that doing philosophy could help us acquire new knowledge,
satisfying the desire for answers to unanswered questions.[6]
I also think Bell is correct that the more curious we are, the more we need
philosophy, and the more we do philosophy, the more curious we become. However,
that Bell is correct to make these two points explains precisely why we should
posit boredom rather than curiosity as the pain that doing philosophy prevents.
As I previously explained, the Epicureans develop a version of desire satisfaction
theory that complements their hedonism, according to which we should eliminate
all desires that are not natural and/or necessary for happiness conceived as
tranquility. The reason for this is simple: wanting some object and then not
getting it is painful and what is painful is to be avoided for the hedonist.
Setting aside the question of whether the desire for knowledge that
curiosity-driven philosophy satisfies is natural and/or necessary for happiness—although
I suspect that the answer to this question is ‘no’ because the knowledge
generated by philosophizing about theoretical physics, for example, is probably
not necessary for tranquility—the fact that there is a feedback loop between
curiosity and doing philosophy means that the desire for curiosity-driven
philosophical knowledge is problematic and ought to be eliminated. The
Epicurean poet Lucretius condemns love insofar as desire for one’s beloved is
problematic because the more we satisfy it, the stronger the desire becomes,
and the harder it becomes to satisfy (4.1089 [2009]).
According to Lucretius, being with a lover is like drinking sea water while
thirsty: it makes you thirstier. Lucretius’ underlying point is that we should
eliminate desires of this kind because desires that are difficult to satisfy
generate obstacles for one’s tranquility insofar as not getting what we want is
painful. As such, if Bell is correct that doing philosophy is worthwhile
because it satisfies our curiosity but also makes us even more curious,
creating demand for more philosophy, then curiosity is like desire for the
beloved and thus ought to be eliminated; it would not be a desire the tranquil
Epicurean should cultivate to make doing philosophy worthwhile.
Second, Bell is also probably correct that the connection
between curiosity and doing philosophy is tighter than the connection between
boredom and doing philosophy in the sense that philosophizing is only one of
many ways to counteract boredom whereas philosophy is one of only a few ways to
sate curiosity. However, for reasons similar to those that I provided in
support for my first objection above, the fact that Bell is probably correct to
observe that the pain of curiosity is more specifically relieved by doing
philosophy is precisely why the Epicurean would be misguided to posit it as
what makes philosophizing worthwhile to the tranquil. According to Epicurean
desire satisfaction theory, we should aim to have desires that can be satisfied
in many ways rather than desires that can only be satisfied in one or even a
few ways. Again: wanting an object and not getting it is painful, and what is
painful is to be avoided, so all things being equal we should prefer to desire
objects that can be readily obtained, and the more ways there are to satisfy a
desire, the more ways there are to obtain what it is that we want. One
Epicurean doctrine is that “[o]ne should bring this question to bear on all of
one’s desires: what will happen to me if what is sought by desire is achieved,
and what will happen if it is not?” (VS 71 [1994]). The
answer to the latter question is that one will be dissatisfied, which will be painful,
and this is why it is better to have desires that can be satisfied in many
ways. In fact, Lucretius uses this very point to provide another argument
against love in De rerum natura (2009). Love creates a singular desire for
the beloved, with whom we cannot always be, and so we feel painful
dissatisfaction in the absence of the beloved. In response, Lucretius somewhat
crudely recommends eliminating this singular desire by satisfying the
underlying want with many objects; he proposes that lovers get over their
unique desire for one another by having sex with other people (4.1057-1072 [2009]).[7]
All of these texts provide evidence that the Epicureans encourage the
cultivation of desires that can be satisfied in many ways. As such, to the
extent that the pain of boredom can be satisfied in many ways and doing
philosophy is only one of them, whereas the pain of curiosity can be satisfied
in far fewer ways but still via philosophy, doing philosophy is more plausibly
rendered worthwhile to the tranquil Epicurean because of the boredom it
counteracts.
3. An Epicurean MAC
Model of Boredom
One problem with my
proposal is that I have not even attempted to describe what an Epicurean
account of boredom would look like. In the absence of any such description, it
remains unclear whether the Epicureans could even have an account of boredom.
If they cannot, then my claim that philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil
Epicurean because it prevents painful boredom they would otherwise experience
would be mistaken. In this section, I determine whether the Epicureans are in a
position to have an account of boredom, and if they are, what such an account
would need to look like. In the following pages, I explain which features an
Epicurean account of boredom would need to possess, determine whether an
account of boredom that possesses all those features exists, and if so, whether
it coheres with key Epicurean tenets.
First, an Epicurean account of boredom would need the
experience of boredom to be painful. If the experience of boredom were not
painful, then avoiding or eliminating the painful sensation associated with it
could not be worthwhile on hedonic grounds. If this were the case, then an
experience, activity, etc. could not be worthwhile for the sake of preventing
or eliminating the experience of boredom qua painful, which is what would need
to be the case for my view to work. After all, my very proposal is that
philosophy is worthwhile even to the tranquil Epicurean because it helps her
avoid or eliminate boredom. Fortunately, there is considerable psychological
evidence that the experience of boredom is painful, which the modern Epicurean
could use to support their claim that the prevention and/or elimination of
boredom is worthwhile on hedonic grounds, which makes philosophy worthwhile,
provided that doing philosophy is the sort of activity that can prevent and/or
eliminate boredom. Wilson et al. (2014) found
that individuals do not enjoy being by themselves with nothing to do, prefer to
administer electrical shocks to themselves instead of being alone with their
thoughts, and, generally, would rather do something over nothing even if the
something is negative. Havermans et al. (2015) found
that participants in a study ate more M&Ms and even self-administered brief
electrical shocks when driven by the desire to escape monotony. A later study
by Nederkoorn at al. (2016) even showed that the function of
the self-administered shocks in the original study was to disrupt monotony.
Apparently, boredom is perceived to be so painful that individuals are willing
to experience a negative but less painful sensation, e.g., a brief electrical
shock, in order to distract themselves from the greater pain of monotony
associated with experience of boredom. As Westgate and Wilson (2018, p. 17) put it, boredom “is a highly aversive
state”. All of this is water for my mill. If boredom is this aversive, then the
tranquil Epicurean will find boredom painful and desire not to experience it.
Consequently, they will need an experience, activity, etc. to prevent or
eliminate boredom, which would then be worthwhile on hedonic grounds. The
question thus becomes whether philosophy can play the role that I have
suggested it does, i.e., whether philosophizing is an activity that prevents
and/or eliminates boredom for a tranquil Epicurean.
Westgate and Wilson (2018) develop
what they call the Meaning and Attention Components (MAC) Model of Boredom.
According to the MAC model of boredom, “boredom is an affective indicator of
unsuccessful attentional engagement in valued goal-congruent activity” (2018, p. 20). On the MAC model, we experience
boredom when we cannot attend successfully to whatever it is to which we are
supposed to be attending and/or the activity in which we are supposed to be
attending lacks adequate value. Westgate and Wilson (2018, p. 20) arrive at this account of boredom
after finding that “attention and meaning are independent causes of boredom”.
Many previous accounts of boredom held that boredom is caused by either a lack
of attention or a lack of meaning but not both. For example, attentional
theories claim that boredom results from a lack of attention, i.e., we tend to
experience boredom when we cannot attend successfully to some activity
(Eastwood et al., 2012; Fisher, 1993; Hamilton, 1981; Leary et al., 1986; Smith and Ellsworth, 1985). Functional theories claim that we
experience boredom when an activity lacks meaning and the function of boredom
is to signal that the activity is insufficiently meaningful (Barbalet, 1999; Chater and Loewenstein, 2016; Locke and Latham, 1990; Van Tilburg and Igou, 2017). The MAC model of boredom holds that
attentional and functional theories are correct and compatible. In other words,
“there are two crucial pieces of information boredom provides – first, whether
there is successful cognitive engagement in the current task (attentional
component) and second, whether the current task, regardless of engagement, is
valuable and thus worth pursuing” (Westgate and Wilson 2018, p. 5).
Presupposing the MAC model of boredom, my claim that
doing philosophy is worthwhile to the tranquil because it prevents painful
boredom they might otherwise experience works only if 1) the tranquil Epicurean
is capable of attending to doing philosophy while tranquil and 2) doing
philosophy while tranquil has adequate value to make it worthwhile. At first
glance, it might seem obvious that doing philosophy will keep the tranquil
Epicurean’s attention so that a tranquil Epicurean who does philosophy will not
experience boredom due to some attentional deficit. Sure, my proposal would
fail if the tranquil Epicurean were incapable of attending to philosophy after
achieving tranquility, but the tranquil Epicurean seems more than capable of
keeping their attention focused squarely on philosophical activity even after
freeing themself from bodily and mental pain. After all, it would be somewhat
strange if the most accomplished Epicureans, who devoted their lives to
philosophical activity, all of a sudden became incapable of attending to
philosophy upon achieving tranquility. However, attending successfully to an
activity is more complicated than it might seem. As Westgate and Wilson (2018) point out, although an attentional deficit
can cause boredom, this deficit can result from a mismatch between one’s
resources and difficulty of the activity attended to. Put otherwise,
attentional deficit and thereby boredom result from both under and
overstimulation. My interpretation must therefore navigate a thin line. Doing
philosophy must be worthwhile to the tranquil because it prevents painful
boredom they might otherwise experience, but, in turn, the activity of
philosophy cannot be too demanding or too underwhelming to them. If philosophy
were too under or overstimulating to them, then it might actually cause boredom
for the tranquil Epicurean, whereas on my view the very function of philosophy
is to prevent such boredom in the first place. Doing philosophy could backfire
for the tranquil Epicurean.
Fortunately, this worry is defeasible. As long as there
is no attentional mismatch between a tranquil Epicurean and the philosophical
project they undertake in order to prevent boredom from setting in, philosophy
could continue to be worthwhile to them to the extent that it staves off
painful boredom. At the same time, for my interpretation to work, the Epicurean
must be careful not to undertake philosophical projects that would be
insufficiently or excessively stimulating for them. Interestingly enough, there
is some evidence in the primary texts that the Epicureans were aware of the
differences in aptitude that existed among them and took these differences into
account when they considered what would be appropriate for each of them. At the
end of the Letter to Herodotus,
Epicurus writes that even a summary of the most important points about the
nature of the universe “would be able to make a man incomparably stronger than
other men, even if he does not go on to all of the precise details of
individual doctrines” (Ep. Hdt. 83 [1994]).
Epicurus knows that not every Epicurean is interested in or even capable of
studying the minutia of atomistic physics. The tranquil Epicurean who
philosophizes to prevent boredom must keep this in mind and do philosophy that
is appropriate to them given their philosophical aptitude. Epicurus himself
might find philosophizing about anything other the minutia of atomistic physics
insufficiently stimulating whereas less philosophically advanced Epicureans
might find philosophizing about this too difficult a topic to manage. According
to Seneca, Epicurus was aware that different Epicureans require different kinds
of assistance in their quest for truth. Apparently, some required no help from
teachers, while others required only a little, and some even needed
encouragement and to be “forced along” into righteousness (Sen. Ep. 52.3-4 [1994]). We can say the same about what kind of philosophy the tranquil
Epicurean should do to prevent painful boredom. The most advanced might need to
philosophize about more difficult topics, whereas the less advanced would need
to philosophize about less difficult topics. Provided there is no attentional
mismatch, philosophy could be worthwhile to prevent boredom.
At this point, I have argued that the Epicureans have the
resources to develop an account of boredom that satisfies one of the two
conditions of Westgate and Wilson’s MAC model. As long as the tranquil
Epicurean philosophizes about topics that are neither insufficiently nor
excessively stimulating to them, aversive boredom would not result from
attentional mismatch. What about the meaning component of the MAC model?
According to Westgate and Wilson, attentional match is necessary but not
sufficient for not being bored. An activity must also be meaningful, otherwise
we might feel bored when we participate in it even if we are capable of
attending to it successfully. For example, Van Tilburg and Igou (2012) found that participants in a study reported
that copying references from a Wikipedia article about concrete was boring
because the participants thought that doing so served no purpose and made them
want to do a task with more meaning. This might explain why Chin et al. (2017) found that the wealthy are less likely to experience boredom that
results from meaninglessness: since the wealthy have more autonomy in choosing
their activities, they are free to choose activities that are more meaningful
to them, and thus experience less boredom as a result than others might.
Whatever the case, for philosophy to play the role that my
interpretation would have it play, the tranquil Epicurean would need to find
doing philosophy meaningful. I have already made the case that the Epicurean
who has achieved tranquility will still find philosophy worthwhile. In fact, my
interpretation takes this to be an explanandum
of Epicurean ethics, one I venture to explain. On my interpretation, there
are primary Epicurean texts indicating that the Epicurean will find
philosophizing worthwhile even after achieving tranquility, the texts I
reviewed in section 2 of this article. However, the Epicureans do not
explicitly offer any explanation for why doing philosophy would be worthwhile
in such circumstances. In fact, it is somewhat difficult to see whether there
could be any such explanation for this if there really are no pleasures to
pursue once we achieve tranquility and hedonism is true so that an experience,
activity, etc. is only worthwhile for the sake of pleasure. Nevertheless, I
think that there is such an explanation available: philosophy is worthwhile to
the Epicurean who achieves tranquility because it counteracts painful boredom they
might otherwise experience. In this respect, my interpretation already
satisfies the meaning criterion of the MAC model of boredom. An experience,
activity, etc. is worthwhile on hedonic grounds only if it produces pleasure
and/or prevents and/or eliminates pain. Even for the tranquil, doing philosophy
prevents pain, e.g., aversive boredom. Thus, philosophy is worthwhile even for
the tranquil because of the boredom it counteracts. If an experience, activity,
etc. is worthwhile, then it is certainly meaningful. Indeed, an activity’s
being meaningful is a necessary condition for its being worthwhile in the sense
that if the activity did not have any meaning in the first place, then it could
not even be worthwhile all-things-considered. As such, to the extent that my solution
shows doing philosophy is worthwhile even to the tranquil, it follows that
philosophizing must also have meaning for the tranquil.
4. Conclusion
From the inside of
Epicurean ethics, there is a puzzle about how anything could be worthwhile to
someone who has achieved the final telos:
tranquility, i.e., freedom from bodily and mental pain. To the extent that an
experience, activity, etc. can only be worthwhile for the sake of eliminating
bodily and mental pain, once all these pains are eliminated, there is nothing
to make doing anything worthwhile. I think that there must be an explanation
for why some things are worthwhile to the tranquil Epicurean because the
primary texts indicate that some things are always worthwhile, even to the
tranquil, e.g., doing philosophy. I have argued (2021) that one explanation for why doing philosophy is worthwhile even to the
tranquil is that philosophizing prevents boredom that the tranquil might
experience without it. In response, Bell argues that the Epicureans do not need
the sort of explanation I offer because lasting tranquility is rare if not
impossible, and even if this were false, a better solution would take
philosophy to be worthwhile to the tranquil because of the curiosity it
satisfies rather than the boredom it prevents. I argued here that the
Epicureans do need the sort of explanation I offered and that Bell’s
explanation is less attractive than mine. However, I also concede that my
explanation requires an account of Epicurean boredom, which I then sketched.
Borrowing from Westgate and Wilson’s (2018) MAC model
of boredom, I argued that in order for doing philosophy to be worthwhile to the
tranquil because it prevents boredom, the relation between boredom and
philosophy must meet three conditions: 1) boredom must be an aversive state, 2)
the Epicurean must be able to attend to philosophy while tranquil, and 3)
philosophizing must have value for the tranquil. I argued that all three
conditions are satisfied by the view that philosophy is worthwhile to tranquil
Epicureans because it helps them to avoid painful boredom.
References
Aristotle (1982). The Complete Works of Aristotle. Princeton
University Press.
Bailey, C. (1928). The Greek
Atomists and Epicurus. Russell and Russell.
Barbalet,
J. (1999). Boredom and Social Meaning. British
Journal of Sociology, 50,
631–646. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-4446.1999.00631.x
Bell,
J. (2021). Epicurean Philosophy, Change, and Curiosity. Southwest Philosophy Review, 37(2),
37–40. https://doi.org/10.5840/swphilreview202137233
Bignone, E. (1973). L’Aristotle perduto e la formazione filosofica di Epicuro (vol. 1).
La Nuova Italia.
Chater,
N., and Loewenstein, G. (2016). The Under-Appreciated Drive for Sense-Making. Journal of Economic Behavior &
Organization, 126,
137–154. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.jebo.2015.10.016
Chin, A., Markey, A., Bhargava, S., Kassam, K. S., and Loewenstein, G. (2017). Bored in the USA: Experience Sampling and Boredom in Everyday Life. Emotion, 17(2), 359–368. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000232
Diano, C. (1943). Note Epicuree. Annali Della R. Scuola Normale Superiore di Pisa. Lettere, Storia e Filosofia, 12(3), 111–123.
Eastwood,
J., Frischen, A., Fenske, M., and Smilek, D. (2012). The Unengaged Mind:
Defining Boredom in Terms of Attention. Perspectives
on Psychological Science, 7,
482–495. https://doi.org/10.1177/17456916124560
Fisher,
C. (1993). Boredom at Work: A Neglected Concept. Human Relations, 46,
395–417. https://doi.org/10.1177/001872679304600305
Gillham,
A. R. (2021). Epicurean Tranquility and the Pleasure of Philosophy. Southwest Philosophy Review,
37(1), 149–158. https://doi.org/10.5840/swphilreview202137116
Havermans,
R. C., Vancleef, L., Kalamatianos, A, and Nederkoorn, C. (2015). Eating and
Inflicting Pain out of Boredom. Appetite,
52–57. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.appet.2014.11.007
Inwood,
B., and Gerson, L. (1994). The Epicurus
Reader. Hackett.
Leary,
M., Rogers, P., Canfield, R., and Coe, C. (1986). Boredom in Interpersonal
Encounters: Antecedents and Social Implications. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 51, 968–975. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.51.5.968
Lucretius.
(2009). De rerum natura. Cambridge University Press.
Locke,
E., and Latham, G. (1990). A Theory of
Goal Setting and Task Performance. Prentice.
Nederkoorn,
C., Vancleef, L., Wilkenhöner, A., Claes, L., and Havermans, R. C. (2016).
Self-Inflicted Pain out of Boredom. Psychiatry
Research, 237,
127–132. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.psychres.2016.01.063
Rist,
J. (1972). Epicurus: An Introduction.
Cambridge University Press.
Smith,
C., and Ellsworth, P. (1985). Patterns of Cognitive Appraisal in Emotion. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology,
48, 813–828. https://doi.org/10.1037/0022-3514.48.4.813
Van
Tilburg, W. A. P., and Igou, E. R. (2012). On Boredom: Lack of Challenge and
Meaning as Distinct Boredom Experiences. Motivation
and Emotion, 36,
181–194. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11031-011-9234-9
Van
Tilburg, W. A. P., and Igou, E. R. (2017). Boredom Begs to Differ:
Differentiation from Other Negative Emotions. Emotion, 17,
309–322. https://doi.org/10.1037/emo0000233
Westgate,
E. C., and Wilson, T. D. (2018). Boring Thoughts and Bored Minds: The MAC Model
of Boredom and Cognitive Engagement. Psychological
Review, 125(5), 689–713. https://doi.org/10.1037/rev0000097
Wilson,
T. D., Reinhard, D. A., Westgate, E. C., Gilbert, D. T., Ellerbeck, N., Hahn, C.,
Brown, C. L., and Shaked, A. (2014). Just Think: The Challenges of the
Disengaged Mind. Science,
345, 75–77. https://doi.org/10.1126/science.1250830
[1] An intrinsic good
is desirable in and of itself, not because of what it causes or leads to. For
the remainder of the article, by ‘good’ I mean desirable and worth having. By ‘bad’
I mean undesirable and worth avoiding.
[2] By ‘good life’ I
mean the life that Epicureans find worth living and therefore try to lead.
[3] Unless noted
otherwise, translations of Epicurean texts are from Inwood and Gerson (1994). I use
abbreviations for primary sources: Ep. Men. = Letter to Menoeceus; Ep. Hdt. = Letter
to Herodotus; VS = Vatican Sayings;
KD = Principal Doctrines; DL = Diogenes Laertius’ Lives of Eminent Philosophers; Sen. Ep. = Seneca’s Epistles, etc.
[4] This is the
standard interpretation of the distinction between kinetic and katastematic
pleasure, championed by Bailey (1928) and Bignone (1973). Alternative interpretations include Diano’s (1943) and Rist’s (1972).
[5] That one can be
happy while being tortured might surprise the modern reader. Then again, if
virtue is sufficient for happiness and one can be virtuous while being
tortured, then it follows that happiness and being tortured are compatible. On
the other hand, even Aristotle writes in the Nicomachean Ethics (1153b19 [1982]) that those who defend such a claim are talking
nonsense. Nevertheless, the fact that Aristotle takes time to explain why he
thinks that this claim is nonsense provides evidence that other philosophers
must have defended it, Epicurus being one of them.
[6] This is not to say
that we can answer all questions by doing philosophy. Nevertheless, the process
of philosophizing might be worthwhile even if the question about which the
Epicurean philosophizes goes ultimately unanswered. However, on Bell’s
solution, we can avoid this complication by recommending that the Epicurean
philosophize primarily about questions that they might reasonably expect to be
answered by doing philosophy.
[7] I should clarify
that many of the Epicurean views I describe in this paper are not my own.
Lucretius might sound somewhat judgmental here and I do not share this
position. However, I am trying to determine in this paper whether the
Epicureans have the resources to explain how philosophy is worthwhile to the
tranquil because it prevents boredom, and such an explanation would need to be
consistent with other Epicurean claims, e.g., Lucretius’.